the role of intuition in philosophy
education and the ways in which these aims can be pursued or achieved. (Intuitions often play the role that observation does in science they are data that must be explained, confirmers or the falsifiers of theories, wrote one philosopher.) Recently, there have been many worries raised with regards to philosophers reliance on intuitions. 5In these broad terms we can see why Peirce would be attracted to a view like Reids. But in the same quotation, Peirce also affirms fallibilism with respect to both the operation and output of common sense: some of those beliefs and habits which get lumped under the umbrella of common sense are merely obiter dictum. The so-called first principles of both metaphysics and common sense are open to, and must sometimes positively require, critical examination. 48While Peirces views about the appropriateness of relying on intuition and instinct in inquiry will vary, there is another related concept il lume naturale which Peirce consistently presents as appropriate to rely on. Similarly, in the passage from The First Rule of Logic, Peirce claims that inductive reasoning faces the same requirement: on the basis of a set of evidence there are many possible conclusions that one could reach as a result of induction, and so we need some other court of appeal for induction to work at all. Although the concept of intuition has a central place in experimental philosophy, it is still far from being clear. What am I doing wrong here in the PlotLegends specification? (eds) Images, Perception, and Knowledge. We thank our audience at the 2017 Canadian Philosophical Association meeting at Ryerson University for a stimulating discussion of the main topics of this paper. This could work as hypothesis for a positive determination, couldn't it? Intuitive consciousness has no goal in mind and is therefore a way of being in the world which is comfortable with an ever-changing fluidity and uncertainty, which is very different from our every-day way of being in the world. The natural light, then, is one that is provided by nature, and is reflective of nature. 3 See, for example, Atkins 2016, Bergman 2010, Migotti 2005. WebThe Role of Intuition in Philosophical Practice by WANG Tinghao Master of Philosophy This dissertation examines the recent arguments against the Centrality thesisthe thesis investigates the relationship between education and society and the ways in which, Chemistry: The Central Science (Theodore E. Brown; H. Eugene H LeMay; Bruce E. Bursten; Catherine Murphy; Patrick Woodward), Educational Research: Competencies for Analysis and Applications (Gay L. R.; Mills Geoffrey E.; Airasian Peter W.), Business Law: Text and Cases (Kenneth W. Clarkson; Roger LeRoy Miller; Frank B. Carrie Jenkins (2014) summarizes some of the key problems as follows: (1) The nature, workings, target(s) and/or source(s) of intuitions are unclear. encourage students to reflect on their own experiences and values. On the basis of the maps alone there is no way to tell which one is actually correct; nor is there any way to become better at identifying correct maps in the future, provided we figure out which one is actually right in this particular instance. Nevertheless, common sense judgments for Reid do still have epistemic priority, although in a different way. Jenkins Carrie, (2008), Grounding Concepts, Oxford, Oxford University Press. A key part of James position is that doxastically efficacious beliefs are permissible when one finds oneself in a situation where a decision about what to believe is, among other things, forced. Indeed, this ambivalence is reflective of a fundamental tension in Peirces epistemology, one that exists between the need to be a fallibilist and anti-skeptic simultaneously: we need something like common sense, the intuitive, or the instinctual to help us get inquiry going in the first place, all while recognizing that any or all of our assumptions could be shown to be false at a moments notice. ), Albany, State University of New York Press. This is why when the going gets tough, Peirce believes that instinct should take over: reason, for all the frills it customarily wears, in vital crises, comes down upon its marrow-bones to beg the succor of instinct (RLT 111). identities. If concepts are also occurring spontaneously, without much active, controlled thinking taking place, then is the entire knowledge producing activity very transitory as seems to be implied? He raises issues similar to (1) throughout his Questions Concerning Certain Faculties, where he argues that we are unable to distinguish what we take to be intuitive from what we take to be the result of processes of reasoning. We argue that all of these concepts are importantly connected to common sense for Peirce. Even deeper, instincts are not immune to revision, but are similarly open to calibration and correction to being refined or resisted. Instinct is more basic than reason, in the sense of more deeply embedded in our nature, as our sharing it with other living sentient creatures suggests. This includes debates about the potential benefits and In fact, to the extent that Peirces writings grapple with the challenge of constructing his own account of common sense, they do so only in a piecemeal way. promote greater equality of opportunity and access to education. But these questions can come apart for Peirce, given his views of the nature of inquiry. Bergman Mats, (2010), Serving Two Masters: Peirce on Pure Science, Useless Things, and Practical Applications, in MatsBergman, SamiPaavola, AhtiVeikkoPietarinen & HenrikRydenfelt (eds. That the instinct of bees should lead them to success is no doubt the product of their nature: evolution has guided their development in such a way to be responsive to their environment in a way that allows them to thrive. (CP 2.178). 10 In our view: for worse. Thus, cognitions arise not from singular previous cognitions, but by a process of cognition (CP 5.267). pp. In itself, no curve is simpler than another [] But the straight line appears to us simple, because, as Euclid says, it lies evenly between its extremities; that is, because viewed endwise it appears as a point. In Michael DePaul & William Ramsey (eds.). For instance, it is obvious that a three-legged stool has three legs or that the tallest building is This includes (CP2.178). In CPR A68/B93 we read that "whereas all intuitions, as sensible, rest on affections, concepts rest on functions", which suggests that intuitions might be akin to what is now called "qualia", but without the subjective/psychological connotation. We have shown that this problem has a contemporary analogue in the form of the metaphilosophical debate concerning reliance on intuitions: how can we reconcile the need to rely on the intuitive while at the same time realizing that our intuitions are highly fallible? Purely symbolic algebraic symbols could be "intuitive" merely because they represent particular numbers.". How Stuff Works - Money - Is swearing at work a good thing. While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. We now turn to intuitions and common sense in contemporary metaphilosophy, where we suggest that a Peircean intervention could prove illuminating. Of course, bees are not trying to develop complex theories about the nature of the world, nor are they engaged in any reasoning about scientific logic, and are presumably devoid of intellectual curiosity. Consider, for example, the following passage from Philosophy and the Conduct of Life (1898): Reasoning is of three kinds. The reason is the same reason why Reid attributed methodological priority to common sense judgments: if all cognitions are determined by previous cognitions, then surely there must, at some point in the chain of determinations, be a first cognition, one that was not determined by anything before it, lest we admit of an infinite regress of cognitions. Peirce does at times directly address common sense; however, those explicit engagements are relatively infrequent. Without such a natural prompting, having to search blindfold for a law which would suit the phenomena, our chance of finding it would be as one to infinity. In these accumulated experiences we possess a treasure-store which is ever close at hand, and of which only the smallest portion is embodied in clear articulate thought. How is 'Pure Intuition' possible according to Kant? There are of course other times at which our instincts and intuitions can lead us very much astray, and in which we need to rely on reasoning to get back on track. Because such intuitions are provided to us by nature, and because that class of the intuitive has shown to lead us to the truth when applied in the right domains of inquiry, Peirce will disagree with (5): it is, at least sometimes, naturalistically appropriate to give epistemic weight to intuitions. As such, intuition is thought of as an original, independent source of knowledge, since it is designed to account for just those kinds of knowledge that other sources do not provide. Here I will stay till it begins to give way. Of these, the most interesting in the context of common sense are the grouping, graphic, and gnostic instincts.8 The grouping instinct is an instinct for association, for bringing things or ideas together in salient groupings (R1343; Atkins 2016: 62). WebThe Role of Intuition in Thinking and Learning: Deleuze and the Pragmatic Legacy Semetsky, Inna Educational Philosophy and Theory, v36 n4 p433-454 Sep 2004 The purpose of this paper is to address the concept of "intuition of education" from the pragmatic viewpoint so as to assert its place in the cognitive, that is inferential, learning process. students to find meaning and purpose in their lives and to develop their own personal Michael DePaul and William Ramsey (eds) rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry. However, upon examining a sample of teaching methods there seemed to be little reference to or acknowledgement of intuitive learning or teaching. How not to test for philosophical expertise. We have seen that this normative problem is one that was frequently on Peirces mind, as is exemplified in his apparent ambivalence over the use of the intuitive in inquiry. To get an idea it is perhaps most illustrative to look back at Peirces discussion of il lume naturale. 42The gnostic instinct is perhaps most directly implicated in the conversation about reason and common sense. But that this is so does not mean, on Peirces view, that we are constantly embroiled in theoretical enterprise. For a discussion of habituation in Peirces philosophy, see Massecar 2016. We all have a natural instinct for right reasoning, which, within the special business of each of us, has received a severe training by its conclusions being constantly brought into comparison with experiential results. Given Peirces thoroughgoing empiricism, it is unsurprising that we should find him critical of intuition in that sense, which is not properly intuition at all. It has little to do with the modern colloquial meaning, something like what Peirce called "instinct for guessing right". Webintuition, in philosophy, the power of obtaining knowledge that cannot be acquired either by inference or observation, by reason or experience. That common sense for Peirce lacks the kind stability and epistemic and methodological priority ascribed to it by Reid means that it will be difficult to determine when common sense can be trusted.2. It counts as an intuition if one finds it immediately compelling but not if one accepts it as an inductive inference from ones intuitively finding that in this, that, and the technology in education and the ways in which technology can be used to facilitate or ), Intuitions, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 91-115. Instead, grounded intuitions are the class of the intuitive that will survive the scrutiny generated by genuine doubt. ); vii and viii, A.Burks (ed. That reader will be disappointed. Indeed, Peirce notes that many things that we used to think we knew immediately by intuition we now know are actually the result of a kind of inference: some examples he provides are our inferring a three-dimensional world from the two-dimensional pictures that are projected on our retinas (CP 5.219), that we infer things about the world that are occluded from view by our visual blind spots (CP 5.220), and that the tones that we can distinguish depend on our comparing them to other tones that we hear (CP 5.222). 9Although we have seen that in contrasting his views with the common-sense Scotch philosophers Peirce says a lot of things about what is view of common sense is not, he does not say a lot about what common sense is. Greco John, (2011), Common Sense in Thomas Reid, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 41.1, 142-55. A significant aspect of Reids notion of common sense is the role he ascribes to it as a ground for inquiry. 13 Recall that the process of training ones instincts up in a more reasonable direction can be sparked by a difficulty posed mid-inquiry, but such realignment is not something we should expect to accomplish swiftly. WebThis includes debates about the role of empirical evidence, logical reasoning, and intuition in the acquisition and evaluation of knowledge and the extent to which knowledge is But as we will shall see, despite surface similarities, their views are significantly different. Alternate titles: intuitive cognition, intuitive knowledge. Therefore, there is no epistemic role for intuition You could argue that Hales hasn't suitably demonstrated premise 1, and that intuition might play epistemic roles other than for determining the necessary (or, more naturally, the a priori) truths of our theories. What philosophers today mean by intuition can best be traced back to Plato, for whom intuition ( nous) involved a kind of insight into the very nature of things. WebIntuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy. This also seems to be the sense under consideration in the 1910 passage, wherein intuitions might be misconstrued as delusions. This is perhaps surprising, first, because talking about reasoning by appealing to ones natural light certainly sounds like an appeal kind of intuition or instinct, so that it is strange that Peirce should consistently hold it in high regard; and second, because performing inquiry by appealing to il lume naturale sounds similar to a method of fixing beliefs that Peirce is adamantly against, namely the method of the a priori. Moral philosophers from Joseph Butler to G.E. If a law is new but its interpretation is vague, can the courts directly ask the drafters the intent and official interpretation of their law? Why are physically impossible and logically impossible concepts considered separate in terms of probability? Peirce argues that il lume naturale, however, is more likely to lead us to the truth because those cognitions that come as the result of such seemingly natural light are both about the world and produced by the world. In this paper, we argue that getting a firm grip on the role of common sense in Peirces philosophy requires a three-pronged investigation, targeting his treatment of common sense alongside his more numerous remarks on intuition and instinct. We stand with other scholars who hold that Peirce is serious about much of what he says in the 1898 lectures (despite their often ornery tone),3 but there is no similar obstacle to taking the Harvard lectures seriously.4 So we must consider how common sense could be both unchosen and above reproach, but also open to and in need of correction. An acorn has the potential to become a tree; a tree has the potential to become a wooden table. the ways in which teachers can facilitate the learning process. For Buddha, to acquire freedom, one has to understand the nature of desires. How can what is forced upon one even be open to correction? The process of unpacking much of what Peirce had to say on the related notions of first cognition, instinct, and il lume naturale motivate us to close by extending this attitude in a metaphilosophical way, and into the 21st century. investigates the relationship between education and society and the ways in which. Even the second part of the process (conceptual part) he describes in the telling phrase: "spontaneity in the production of concepts". rev2023.3.3.43278. A Noetic Theory of Understanding and Intuition as Sense-Maker. Intuitions are psychological entities, but by appealing to grounded intuitions, we do not merely appeal to some facts about our psychology, but to facts about the actual world. As Peirce thinks that we are, at least sometimes, unable to correctly identify our intuitions, it will be difficult to identify their nature. These are currently two main questions addressed in contemporary metaphilosophical debates: a descriptive question, which asks whether intuitions do, in fact, play a role in philosophical inquiry, and a normative question, which asks what role intuitions ought to play a role in such inquiry. 35At first pass, examining Peirces views on instinct does not seem particularly helpful in making sense of his view of common sense, since his references to instinct are also heterogeneous. In this paper, we argue that getting a firm grip on the role of common sense in Peirces philosophy requires a three-pronged investigation, targeting his treatment of common sense alongside his more numerous remarks on intuition and instinct. 81We started with a puzzle: Peirce both states his allegiance to the person who contents themselves with common sense and insists that common sense ought not have any role to play in many areas of inquiry. Boyd Kenneth & Diana Heney, (2017), Rascals, Triflers, and Pragmatists: Developing a Peircean Account of Assertion, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 25.2, 1-22. He disagrees with Reid, however, about what these starting points are like: Reid considers them to be fixed and determinate (Peirce says that although the Scotch philosophers never wrote down all the original beliefs, they nevertheless thought it a feasible thing, and that the list would hold good for the minds of all men from Adam down (CP5.444)), but for Peirce such propositions are liable to change over time (EP2: 349). When these instincts evolve in response to changes produced in us by nature, then, we are then dealing with il lume naturale. This entry addresses the nature and epistemological role of intuition by considering the following questions: (1) What are intuitions?, (2) What roles do they serve in philosophical (and other armchair) inquiry?, (3) Ought they serve such roles?, (4) What are the implications of the empirical investigation of intuitions for their proper roles?, 49To figure out whats going on here we need to look in more detail at what, exactly, Peirce thought il lume naturale referred to, and how it differed from other similar concepts like instinct and intuition. This becomes apparent in his 1898 The First Rule of Logic, where Peirce argues that induction on the basis of facts can only take our reasoning so far: The only end of science, as such, is to learn the lesson that the universe has to teach it. DePaul and W. Ramsey (eds. Thanks also to our wonderful co-panelists on that occasion, who gathered with us to discuss prospects for pragmatism in the 21st century: Shannon Dea, Pierre-Luc Dostie Proulx, and Andrew Howat. ), Rethinking Intuition (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998). 4For Reid, common sense is polysemous, insofar as it can apply both to the content of a particular judgment (what he will sometimes refer to as a first principle) and to a faculty that he takes human beings to have that produces such judgments. (CP 5.589). 70It is less clear whether Peirce thinks that the intuitive can be calibrated. With respect to the former, Reid says of beliefs delivered by common sense that [t]here is no searching for evidence, no weighing of arguments; the proposition is not deduced or inferred from another; it has the light of truth in itself, and has no occasion to borrow it from another (Essays VI, IV: 434); with respect to the latter, Reid argues that all knowledge got by reasoning must be built upon first principles. Intuition is immediate apprehension by the understanding. 56We think we can make sense of this puzzle by making a distinction that Peirce is himself not always careful in making, namely that between il lume naturale and instinct. As we will see in what follows, that Peirce is ambivalent about the epistemic status of common sense judgments is reflective of his view that there is no way for a judgment to acquire positive epistemic status without passing through the tribunal of doubt. WebThe Role of Intuition in Philosophical Practice by WANG Tinghao Master of Philosophy This dissertation examines the recent arguments against the Centrality thesisthe thesis that intuition plays central evidential roles in philosophical inquiryand their implications for the negative program in experimental philosophy. Two Experimentalist Critiques, in Booth Anthony Robert & Darrell P. Rowbottom (eds. At the same time, Peirce often states that common sense has an important role to play in both scientific and vital inquiry, and that there cannot be any direct profit in going behind common sense. Our question is the following: alongside a scientific mindset and a commitment to the method of inquiry, where does common sense fit in? ), The Normative Thought of Charles S. Peirce, New York, Fordham University Press. One of the consequences of this view, which Peirce spells out in his Some Consequences of Four Incapacities, is that we have no power of intuition, but every cognition is determined logically by previous cognitions (CP 5.265). Here, then, we want to start by looking briefly at Reids conception of common sense, and what Peirce took the main differences to be between it and his own views. At least at the time of Philosophy and the Conduct of Life, though, Peirce is attempting to make a distinction between inquiry into scientific and vital matters by arguing that we have no choice but to rely on instinct in the case of the latter. Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. The Epistemology of Thought Experiments: First Person versus Third Person Approaches. Michael DePaul and William Ramsey, eds., Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry. 28Far from being untrusting of intuition, Peirce here puts it on the same level as reasoning, at least when it comes to being able to lead us to the truth. 8This is a significant point of departure for Peirce from Reid. Of Logic in General). Is there a single-word adjective for "having exceptionally strong moral principles"? Philosophy Stack Exchange is a question and answer site for those interested in the study of the fundamental nature of knowledge, reality, and existence. The relationship between education and society: Philosophy of education also But they are not the full story. Can I tell police to wait and call a lawyer when served with a search warrant? In doing conceptual examination we are allowing our concepts to guide us, but we need not be aware that they are what is guiding us in order to count as performing an examination of them in my intended sense [] By way of filling in the rest of the story, I want to suggest that, if our concepts are somehow sensitive to the way the independent world is, so that they successfully and accurately represent that world, then an examination of them may not merely be an examination of ourselves, but may rather amount to an examination of an accurate, on-board conceptual map of the independent world. Photo by The Roaming Platypus on Unsplash. The purpose of this paper is to address the concept of "intuition of education" from the pragmatic viewpoint so as to assert its place in the cognitive, that is inferential, learning process. education and the ways in which these aims can be pursued or achieved. ), Essays on Moral Realism, Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 181-228. Thats worrisome, to me, because the whole point of philosophy is allegedly to figure out whether our intuitive judgments make sense. Learn more about Stack Overflow the company, and our products. Peirce suggests that the idealist will come to appreciate the objectivity of the unexpected, and rethink his stance on Reid. There are times, when the sceptic comes calling, to simply sit back and keep your powder dry.
the role of intuition in philosophy